The article delves into David Shoemaker's book, "Wisecracks," which argues that morally questionable humor, such as banter, teasing, and mockery, can be ethically acceptable and even beneficial within certain contexts. It examines the complexities of this claim, using examples from everyday interactions and public controversies surrounding comedians like Dave Chappelle and Jimmy Carr.
Shoemaker analyzes deception, mockery, and stereotyping in humor, highlighting that while they can have negative aspects, their positive effects, such as fostering solidarity and destigmatizing issues, can outweigh the risks.
The article also explores the role of humor in coping with suffering, referencing the coping mechanisms of first responders and the use of comedy in groups like rape survivors. It questions the notion that humor always involves detachment or distraction, suggesting that it can also provide solidarity and a method of transforming negative experiences into something positive.
The article brings in Thomas Nagel's concept of absurdity, suggesting that the recognition of life's inherent meaninglessness can be a source of comic relief. This perspective provides a counterpoint to the view of humor as merely a distraction from pain.
Ultimately, the article presents a nuanced view of humor, highlighting the moral complexities, the risks, and the potential benefits of using humor, especially within the context of close relationships. It concludes that humor, in its many forms, can be a powerful tool for connection, coping, and even overcoming hardship, but the context and intent remain crucial elements.
Professional comedy, which most of us consume in modest doses, is not how humor infuses our day-to-day lives. Nor are proper jokes, with feed lines and punch lines, the primary vehicle for laughter. Instead, top billing goes to the wisecracks we share with family and friendsâthose spontaneously funny, though often mocking, remarks that leaven our daily chatter. When my English-professor wife is forced to spend her morning drafting an email to colleagues instead of working on an essay for a journal, I console her, dryly, that she can always submit her email to the Journal of Administrative Memos. Our queer teen jokes with us about the âBLTâ communityâan affectionate riff on the ever-growing acronym. And when Iâm forced to admit my day job as a philosopher who writes about knowing how to live, I try to puncture the pretension with a postscript: âItâs important to work on the things youâre not good at.â Like I said: not proper jokes, but they were funny at the time.
David Shoemakerâs new book, Wisecracks, is not about comedians, or jokes. Instead, he aims to illuminate the ethics of âbanter, teasing, mockery, prankery, taking the piss, leg-pulling, joshing, and quippery.â Shoemakerâs claim is bold: that morally questionable humor is not just ethically okay but positively good.
A few high-profile cases have shown the extreme side of such humor, among them Dave Chappelle on trans people and Jimmy Carr on Roma and the Holocaust. But Shoemaker turns attention away from public controversy to ordinary life, lowering the rhetorical temperature. Many of us make fun of family and friends, their flaws and foibles, in ways that involve mockery or stereotypingâwisecracks we wouldnât venture in public. Context matters, which makes it hard to offer examples, because the context that makes a wisecrack fine between close friends is very different from the context of an article in The Atlantic. I trust that, like me, you know firsthand the kinds of conversations Shoemaker has in mind. In giving them their due, he sheds new light on the ethics of these everyday interactions.
Shoemaker spends a chapter each on deception, mockery, and stereotyping, arguing that there are moral reasons against all three but that those reasons are often outweighed by the arguments in favor.
âProbably the most familiar type [of put-on] involves getting someone who cares about you to believe that youâve failed at something when youâve actually succeeded,â Shoemaker writesâas when I return glumly from my third driving test only to reveal, to laughing relief, that Iâve finally passed. According to Shoemaker, âPranks and put-ons ⌠require real deception, and that deception is of an immoral sortââa characterization that strikes me as being a little strong. Whatever trickery is involved when I tell you that the word gullible has been taken out of the dictionary, I doubt it warrants the âblaming angerâ Shoemaker explores. Nor is it obvious that friendly mockery causes âembarrassment or humiliationââreactions it may instead defuse. But as it gets more edgy, wisecracking does mean moral risk, leaving open the potential that people may be genuinely deceived, or hurt, or disrespected.
We need good reason to take such risks, because itâs not generally permissible to expose someone to lies or harm merely for oneâs own pleasure. Struggling to see much upside for the victims of pranks in being pranked, Shoemaker comes down pretty hard: âInterpersonal pranks are the lowest form of humor not because they require deception (leg-pulling does that too), but because they often aim to cause intrinsically harmful psychological states.â One of his more extreme examples is the bucket of pigâs blood dumped on the head of the eponymous antihero in Stephen Kingâs Carrie.
But many wisecracks fare betterâincluding those that mock or stereotype. As Shoemaker contends, wisecracking can at times be a source of profound solidarity. When friends make fun of us for what would otherwise be embarrassing mistakes, failures, or foibles, they destigmatize them. When we mock a stereotype that others use for harm, we forge a connection that turns prejudice into subversive pleasure. Shoemakerâs most challenging prescription is a plea for us to joke with close friends about their disabilities, even if the disabilities are not ones we share. To refuse to do so is not just to signal that the disability is too harmful or too shameful for laughter, but to exclude someone from the community of humor: âItâs to discriminate against them in a crucial arena of interpersonal life solely in virtue of some arbitrary impairment or deviation from a physical or psychological ânormâ ⌠Itâs to deprive them of opportunities for engagement and solidarity and bonding that remain open to others. And thatâs immoral.â
This doesnât mean itâs not a delicate enterprise, or that we canât go wrongâbut thereâs a moral argument for mockery, in context. To return to professional comedy, which we initially set aside: I think of Jimmy Carr, performing at a cancer-hospice gig with other comics, noting with discomfort that his peers had been afraid to joke about death. Hastening to the mic for the last spot of the evening, Carr opened with âCâmon, we havenât got much time ⌠well, I haveâ and followed up by asking âIs anyone here from last year?â I believe him when he says that the tension in the room dissolved, for a moment, in laughter. The moral risk paid off.
Humor offers more than just solidarity. It helps us cope with âthe vicissitudes, difficulties, and absurdities of lifeâ by changing our emotional relationship with them, Shoemaker writes. This is perhaps its deepest value and the one that I most cherish. Itâs also the most mysterious.
Shoemaker connects the consoling power of humor with a conception of absurdity proposed by the philosopher Thomas Nagel. Immersed in life, we believe that our work, our interests, our politics, and the people we care about really matter. But, according to Nagel, when we step back and reflect from a cosmic perspective, we find our knowledge of their value fragile or unfounded. We cannot prove they matter at all; life seems absurd. âNagel thinks this absurdity isnât some great tragedy,â Shoemaker writes, seemingly deadpan, âto be addressed only by suicide or Buddhism.â Instead, the recognition that (maybe) nothing matters comes as comic relief: âFrom the point of view of the universe, none of our stakes could be lower, which is what makes humans at the same time so vicious and yet so hilarious.â
Read: The dark art of comedy in Ukraine
Thereâs something in this thought, but it feels like a rim shot to me. The joke does not quite land. What humor helps us confront, I think, is not the insignificance of our existence but the problem of human suffering. Shoemaker quotes Mark Twain: âThe secret source of humor itself is not joy but sorrow. There is no humor in heaven.â He goes on to describe how first responders use humor to cope with trauma: âThey distract and detach.â To join them, he writes, âwe may need to take off our âemotional empathy lenses,â and put on our âpsychopath lensesâââlaughing at pain with âwhat Henri Bergson called âthe momentary anaesthesia of the heart.ââ
Such disengagement may be functional at times, but I donât think itâs the only way that humor helps us cope with hardship. It doesnât fit all of Shoemakerâs own examples. At one point, he writes about comedy revues performed by and for rape survivors: âAs one person in the audience described the show, âI found it 100 per cent more funny than being raped.ââ The point is surely not diversion or emotional numbing. Itâs solidarityâand maybe something more.
When I think about the value of dark humor, I donât think of distraction or detachment, or the possibility that nothing really matters, but of the alchemy by which the worst things we go through can be transmuted into laughter and therefore, momentarily, overcome. How can we take pleasure in what is terrible without cruelty or illusion, without pretending that it wasnât so bad after all or that everything works out for the best? Intellectually, this puzzle may be insoluble. Emotionally, we seem to solve it, sometimes, when we joke about the unacceptable, turning the lead of suffering into the gold, or the foolâs gold, of humor.
âWhen you buy a book using a link on this page, we receive a commission. Thank you for supporting The Atlantic.
Skip the extension â just come straight here.
Weâve built a fast, permanent tool you can bookmark and use anytime.
Go To Paywall Unblock Tool